UNIVERSITY
OF NIGERIA, NSUKKA
FACULTY
OF SOCIAL SCIENCE
DEPARTMENT
OF PHILOSOPHY
TOPIC:
KANTS’ NOTION OF CATEGORY
AN
ASSIGNMENT
SUBMITTED IN
PARTIAL FULFILMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE COURSE: PHIL 211
(METAPHYSIC)
BY
UGWANYI IMELDA.
A. 2013/187178
UGWU OLUCHUKWU
MARY 2013/190802
ORAKWE CHIOMA
ANASTASIA 2013/187166
ODO SOLOMON
ANETOCHUKWU 2013/188496
LECTURER:
REV. FR. DR. INNOCENT ENWEH
JANUARY,
2015.
KANTS’ NOTION OF CATEGORY
Brief
history of Emmanuel Kant
He was born in Konigsberg; East of
Prussia in 1724. His father was a Saddle-Maker. He did his philosophical
studies between 1740 to 1946 after that he tutored till his retirement in 1796.
He died in 1804.
Before his death, he published books
in various areas of study like philosophy, political theory, natural science,
law, history etc. Some of his books include critique of pure Reason (1796), Critique
of practical Reason (1788), Religion within the Bounds of Reason Alone (1792),
Metaphysic of Morals (1797) and so on.
Brief Introduction to the Word Category
The word came from Greek word
‘Kategoria’ meaning that which can be said, predicted or publicly declared and
asserted about something. A category is attribute property, quality or
characteristics that can be predicted of a thing.
The category theory has been a
respectable theory in Western Metaphysics from Aristotle to strawson. It states
that objects of knowledge can metaphysically be divided into a fixed number of
categories. There appears to be four main theories of categories, first,
Aristotle’s Metaphysical theory of Categories, Second, Kant’s epistemological
theory of categories, third, Russell’s Logical theory of types of categories
and fourth, Strawson’s descriptive theory of categories.
In his critique of pure reason, Kant
intends to provide a principle to identify the most fundamental concepts of
thought, the categories of the understanding, and then to show that our
knowledge of any object always involves these categories. Categories are fundamental
concepts that have a function, namely to unify and order the manifold.
Common
Belief in Philosophy Before Kant
Prior to Kant, the common belief
among philosophers was that in the process of acquiring knowledge, objects
imposed themselves on the human mind which passively received them. The mind
was seen as playing a passive role, simply receiving impressions imposed on it
by the objects of sense-perception. The implication of this is that synthentic
a priori knowledge would be impossible. All knowledge would then derive from
sense-perception. Kant reversed the view, and argued that it is not objects
that imposed themselves on the mind, on the contrary it is the mind that
imposed itself, its own structure, on objects, and makes them conform to it. It
makes objects appear to us according to this structure. The result is that we
do not perceive objects the way they are in themselves (noumena) but the way
they appear to us (phenomena). i.e. according to its structure which it imposes
on them. Thus the mind restructures objects to conform to its own structure,
and the only way we can ever know them. The structure of the mind is seen in
the categories of human understanding (12 in number), and it is by means of
these categories that the mind plays a very positive role in acquisition of
knowledge.
Time and space as mind’s necessary categories of perception.
Kant believes
that we human have more categories of perception than the binary computers
have, but that we still perceive everything in terms of our particular
categroeis because our minds can register only what our mind are capable of
registering.
Kant believes that time and space
shape all our perceptious, just as ones and zeroes shape the perceptions of
binary computers. The categories of time include such notions as now and then,
earlier and later, before and after, fast and slow, duration and so on; space
includes notions such as here and there, large and small, near and far, up and
down, high and low around, proximity and so forth. Time and space shape all our
perceptions because our minds are simply incapable of having any perception
except those that are conditioned by time and space. The fact alone, that every
single actual experience we have ever had, without exception, has occurred in
time and space, ought to make us suspicious that time and space are human
construct, things our minds must add to experience in order for the experience
to register with us. Our minds are incapable of even imagining what a timeless
or space-less experience would be like. The fact that we cannot even imagine a
non-time and non-space condition perception ought to make us know that time and
space perception ought to make us know that time and space are the mind’s
necessary categories of perception.
Kant considers space and time to be
the two primary conditioners of all our experience, the two transcendental
forms of perception. But in addition to them, twelve other categories also
condition our experience.
Kant’s Table of Categories
S/N
|
Of
Quantity
|
Of
Quality
|
Of
Relation
|
Of
Modality
|
1.
|
Unity
|
Reality
|
Inherence
and Subsistence
|
Possibility-Impossibility
|
2.
|
Plurality
|
Negation
|
Causality
and dependence
|
Existence-Non-existence
|
3.
|
Totality
|
Limitation
|
Community
(reciprocity between agents and patient)
|
Necessity-Contingence
|
This table of categories
systematically represents and orders all the categories applicable to a particular
domain. It possesses a distinctive structure insofar as they consist of four
headings, with three categories falling under each. According to Kant, we have
this structure because the a priori division of a process of synthesis is
tetrachotomous while that of a synthetic concept is trichotomous. The headings
correspond to sub-functions of the process of synthesis of the manifold. The
categories represent ways in which the manifold can be synthesized, whereby
each heading represents one feature with respect to which synthesis can take
place i.e. the synthesis corresponding to each feature can be understood as a
sub-function and is represented by a way that we have progression, whereby each
sub-function presupposes the previous ones, starting with quantity, which is
the most basic one, followed by quality, relation and modality.
We can divide the categories falling
under the titles into two classes, namely the mathematical and dynamical
categories. The former are the categories of quantity and quality and are
concerned with the practical rule or experience considered in itself
independently of any relation in which it stands. The latter are the categories
of relation and modality and they focus on connections to other objects,
practical rules or experiences.
The categories falling under each
title form a three-fold synthetic unity, whereby the first two produce the
third when jointly combined, without the third category having a derivative
status since it is based on a distinct function of synthesis. The third
category always arises from the combination of the second with the first in its
class. These three categories constitute an exhaustive account of fundamental
principle of synthesis falling within each sub-function. There are precisely
three of them because a synthetic unity requires.
i.
A condition (ii)
a conditioned (iii) the concept which
arises out of combination of the conditioned with its condition.
Summary of the individual categories
1. Quantity
It is concerned with the extension or
domain of practical rule. It determines the domain of applicability for whom
this rule holds. There are:
-
Subjective rules or maxims that hold for the agent (unity)
-
Objective rules or precepts that hold for everyone with the
same indinations (Plurality)
-
Laws that hold for everyone unconditionally and absolutely
(totality)
2. Quality
It determines
what the rules says – it is required for making a command in the same way that
quality is required in judgements for making a claim. It does not specify the
nature of the action but determines wether a particular action is to be
performed or omitted or whether an exception is to be made. There are:
-
Rules that tell us to do x i.e. to commit (reality)
-
Rules that tell us to not do x i.e. to omit (Negation)
-
Rules that tell us to do x even though there is a rule to
not do x, or not to do x even though there is rule to do x i.e. exceptions
(Limitation)
3. Relation
They are
concerned with the relations in which practical rules stand. It is not
concerned with the moral evaluation of rules. The categories concern:
-
Practical rules as inhering in a subject and resulting from
the freedom of that subject (inherence and subsistence)
-
Practical rules that have effects on persons (cause and
effect)
-
Practical rules that imply a reciprocal relation between
agent and patient (community)
N.b:
The first two are always, sub-ordination relation while the third is
co-ordination relation. Kant calls them heteronomic and homonomic relations
respectively.
4. Modality
It concerns the
relation between the rule in question and other rules. It is concerned with the
relational features of practical rules not metaphysical, but logical relations.
It is concerned with how the rule is to be asserted or assessed – as Kant says
with respect to the table of judgement, modality “concerns only the value of
the copula”.
There are
practical rules that necessitate:
-
Problematically (possible-impossible)
-
Assertorically (Existence- Non existence)
-
Apodictically (necessary-contingent)
Conclusion
We would like to conclude by stating
that any interpretation or reconstruction of Kants’ category must meet the
following two general criteria, namely that it must give an account of the
categories such that;
i.
The third category under each heading can be derived from
the combination of the previous two and
ii.
The first two categories must be sensibly conditioned (leads
to satisfaction of a possible end) and morally undetermined, while the third
one is sensibly unconditioned and morally determined (free choice that does not
lead to satisfaction of an end, but rather because it is in itself necessary).

Barder,
R.M. (2009). Kant and the Categories of Freedom Retrieved on December 12, 2014,
from British Journal for the
history of philosophy. Website:http://users.ox.ac.uk/2SFOPO426/Categories%20of%20freedom%20C R%20Bader)pdf press
Immanuel
Kant. Retrieved on December, 12, 2014, Online Journal. Website: http://pdf crowd.com/genpdf/f21dgeOad/b99436bc/d9eOa6c6a/5.pdf.?name=www-text
etc.com - theory –Kant-html.pdf.
Iroegbu, Pantaleon. (1995). Metaphysics: The Kpim of
Philosophy. Owerri: International University
Press Ltd.
Omoregbe, J. I. (1996). Metaphysis: without tears a
systematic and historical study. Lagos: Joja
press Limited.
Omoregbe, J. I. (1998). Epistemology. (Theory of
Knowledge): A systematic and historical Study. Lagos: Joja Press Limited
Some
reflections on Kant’s Category theory. Retrieved on December 12, 2014, from Indian Philosophical
quarterly. Website: http//unipune.ac.in/snc/csshlipq/English/IPQ/11- 15%20Volumes/13%2005%20&%2004/PDF/13-3&4-8.pdf
No comments:
Post a Comment